Harper’s
Folly
“Hysterical Scientism: The
Ecstasy of Richard Dawkins”
What was Harper’s
magazine thinking when they printed this outrageous review of Richard
Dawkins’ The
God Delusion by
Marilynne Robinson?
(November 26, 2006)
As a follow-up to my review of Richard Dawkins’ The God
Delusion and Sam Harris’ Letter
to a Christian Nation (Comment 16),
I must respond to the review of Dawkins’ book by Marilynne Robinson in the November
issue of Harper’s,
and I will do so at some length. It is certainly a curiosity that a
seemingly liberal and outspoken magazine like Harper’s would offer a piece like
this one. The first sign that there
is an a priori prejudice
involved is the title: “Hysterical
Scientism:
The Ecstasy of Richard Dawkins.” This is
not a review, properly
speaking. It is a smug and pretentious defamation of
science and scientists, and Richard Dawkins in particular.
The definition of ‘scientism’
is “The
belief that the principles and methods of the physical and
biological sciences should be applied to other disciplines” (Random House Webster's College Dictionary). In my experience this word is
never employed
by science itself but by those outside science who view it with a
jaundiced
eye. (See Forum 11 for an example.) It is
almost invariably pejorative, accusing science of being an ‘ideology’
which regards itself as the only legitimate way to
investigate and
uncover reality. Perhaps it does, and perhaps it is, but the term’s use
invariably implies the claim that there is “another way of knowing,”
and while I have encountered ‘ways
of knowing’
which include mystical
journeys
in spirit and past lives psychotherapy, the claim is usually made with
an eye
to religious revelation. Now, Robinson never directly discusses
religion as a
legitimate alternative to science—or scientism—but her feelings are
clear
throughout, and she does make this one admission: “The reader may
assume a
somewhat greater admiration on my part for religion in the highest
sense of the
word [in comparison with “science in
the highest sense of the word”
which she
is about to discuss], though I will not go into that here.” So
there is
little
doubt where she is coming from.
Robinson is a
clever and
sophisticated writer (as winner of the Pulitzer Prize and the National
Book Critics
Circle Award for fiction she would have to be), but
her scornful
treatment of Dawkins himself hardly does credit to those talents. The
“full
force of his intellect…verbal skills…and his human learning (is also)
capacious
enough to include some deeply minor poetry.” While Dawkins, in offering
a
smattering of the latter, may be invading Robinson’s territory,
Robinson can
never be accused of invading Dawkins’ scientific one, for her treatment
of
science is so deeply buried in prejudice it is beyond recognition. She
accuses
Dawkins of having his own version of Darwinism. What that may be is not
quite
clear, since while Dawkins champions classic “natural selection” as the
working
principle of evolution, he is hardly ignorant of the nuances of that
principle
and appeals to nothing that I am aware of as being outdated, much less
some
lunatic fringe viewpoint. Perhaps she is referring to quantum theory
(which in
any case Dawkins does discuss), for she seems to have a special use for
that
dimension of science which I will detail later.
The
Demon Science
Robinson is anxious
to fault
science for some of its products—mainly, of course, nuclear weapons—and
scientists for being willing to make them. Her point is not as well
taken as
she thinks. Science as a method of investigation and path to knowledge
about
the world and ourselves is untainted by how some people may
use the
technology proceeding from it. There is nothing in The God
Delusion which makes a blanket defense of technology,
although many uses of science have been of immeasurable benefit to
humankind
(and religionists have often been fighting them every step of the way).
Science
may hopefully save us from our planet being ruined by overpopulation
(driven in
great measure by religion), and give us longer, disease-free lives
(against
opposition
to cures in defense of certain views of morality, or the fate of souls
in a
petrie dish). Nuclear science gave us nuclear energy which has the
potential to
rescue us from the perils of fossil fuel burning. Difficult side
effects may
attend to anything, but they can be overcome; and good things may have
the
potential to be misused, usually by people driven by anything but
rational
motives. That hardly means we should have remained in the Dark Ages to
minimize such potential. And it is only science, in uncovering our real
natures,
which
opens new avenues (certainly religion has long failed) to provide the
means to
disarm our capacity to put good things to bad uses.
Religion, on the
other hand,
discovers nothing and postulates fantasies that directly promote
(usually via
their holy books) war, division and inhumanity, not to mention mental
instability and anguish.
One
of Robinson’s clever
phrases is “the tectonics of culture” which, according to her, are “suddenly
active, and all the old rifts and stresses and pressures that seemed to
have
fallen dormant have awakened at once.” I don’t know what she has in
mind here,
for each age has its rifts and stresses which would hardly lead its
denizens to
regard their time as an age of dormancy. Perhaps she has in mind a
certain past
religious naivete, when belief in the supernatural was widely respected
and atheists hid fearfully in the closet, because
she
offers as an “instance”
of such awakened rifts The
God Delusion, which has arisen out of the clamor to “denounce the
great Satan,
religion.” Certainly from the standpoint of our day, the pressures and
stresses,
whether domestically in the U.S.
or internationally in the Islamist
movement, are the direct products of religion. Those tectonics are
active
precisely because of the instability caused by faith and monumental
superstition carried to fundamentalist extremes. The God
Delusion is not a part of the phenomenon, it is a reaction to it. Would Robinson regard an increase
in the prosecution of criminals as an “instance” of the phenomenon of
criminality?
The Demon Scientists
Robinson makes an
ill-disguised
attempt to brand Dawkins as something akin to a racist, and she does it
with
misleading quotations. (The fact that she doesn’t detail page numbers
for any of
her quotes makes it difficult for the reader to check up on whether
she
has
misrepresented anything.) As part of a context in which Dawkins
criticizes the
divisive ‘in-group’ mentality in most religious settings (Catholic vs.
Protestant, mainly), he also notes that Jews are discouraged from
“marrying
out.” Robinson quotes the latter and then says,
…and [Dawkins] complains that
such “wanton and carefully nurtured divisiveness (is) a significant
force for
evil.” It is of course no criticism to say that he values the
traditions of
Judaism not at all, since this is only consistent with his view of
religion in
general.
This is
dirty pool. First of
all, here is what Dawkins actually says:
Even if religion did no other
harm in itself, its wanton and carefully nurtured divisiveness – its
deliberate
and cultivated pandering to humanity’s natural tendency to favour
in-groups and
shun out-groups – would be enough to make it a significant force for
evil in
the world.
Here he
has moved beyond
Judaism itself and is addressing the in-group mentality of religions in
general, which does indeed nurture divisiveness (and even hatred of
other
humans for believing in a different fantasy than one's own), and this
characteristic feature of religion is indeed a significant force for
evil, as
we can see for ourselves by simply looking around the world. Robinson
presents
it as though Dawkins has made a direct racial attack on Jews and Jewish
culture
as a whole. Would she have said, so-and-so is guilty of not valuing the
traditions of African-Americans because of some criticized feature of
in-group
behavior? Unfortunately, the accusation of anti-Semitism is a handy
tool for
demonization and she uses it more than once, never honestly.
She even manages to
involve
science in the promotion of the Holocaust through the pseudo-scientific
Nazi
eugenics theories which provided a rationale for Jewish inferiority and
eradication. Would anyone label Dr. Mengele a “scientist”? Such people
were
driven by political ideologies and anti-Semitic traditions (having religious roots) that would never be encompassed by
Dawkins’
concept of science, let alone of ‘morality.’ If science, as
demonstrated by
Hitlerian eugenics, is “vulnerable” to cultural prejudice—just as
religion is,
she fails to note—it is equally ‘vulnerable’ to correction, since such
eugenics
have been discredited, not the least
through advances in scientific understanding and the general
enlightenment of
outlook prompted by humanism, which tends to go hand in hand with
scientific
advance. Thus, contrary to Robinson’s claim, science has
proven to supply a correction to the culturally prejudiced,
including those by whom it may have been coopted in the past. (We
should also note that it is precisely science which has revealed that
there is no genetic basis for racial differentiation; this, unlike
anything religion has ever come up with, is our avenue to correcting
such prejudices.)
Bad
Science Vs. Bad Religion
This is
one respect among several
in which Robinson’s attempt to equate “bad science” with “bad religion”
founders. Bad
religion has never corrected itself, because religion is
incapable
of that kind of self-examination and flexibility. Just ask the Vatican. Bad science, on the other hand, will
eventually be found out,
because
scientists are always searching for an improved
science; self-correction is
built into the
scientific method. Religion, on the other hand, boasts of immutability
and
infallibility. When a scientist corrects previous theories, he wins a
Nobel
Prize. When a theist 'corrects' a religion, he’s burned at the stake as
a heretic.
In a
tortured piece of logic,
Robinson tries to justify the 19th century case of the
Catholic
Church in Italy seizing a child of Jewish parents to forcibly
raise him
Christian because they had discovered that he had been baptized several
years
earlier by a concerned babysitter! The implacable logic of the Church
was that
now, intended or not, with a sprinkle of water he was among the saved
and had to be removed from
his
parents’ heretical environment. This is a far more egregious example of
disrespect
toward the Jewish heritage than anything Dawkins is accused of. Yet
Robinson tries
to defend it by pointing out that had the child continued in his Jewish
culture
and community, he might have been caught up in the Nazi Holocaust some
decades
later, a Holocaust which was the product of science! (Nazi eugenics,
remember?) Perhaps one could turn this sort of argument to use against
Robinson’s
criticism of
scientists for manufacturing nuclear weapons. They undoubtedly, in
their MAD
wisdom, prevented a World War III in the latter part of the 20th
century between the West and Communism, since neither side could bring
itself to
let loose such weapons because of the planetary devastation they knew
would
ensue. Unfortunately, religion is not deterred by such pragmatic
considerations.
When you believe God wants you to conquer the world no matter the cost,
that
after death Paradise awaits, so what? Communists were not big on
martyrdom, not
the least because they were atheists.
We are much less likely to find a mechanism to ensure civilization’s
survival
in dealing with religious fanatics. After all, an imam gave Osama bin
Laden
permission to kill up to 10 million infidels in his holy war against
the West,
a goal that could only stand a chance of being achieved if his
religious ‘scientists’
get hold of nuclear weapons. Robinson claims that “science’s capacity
for doing
harm is unequalled.” Rather, it is the political and religious
fanatics’
capacity
to turn science to their destructive ends which possesses a capability
of
that
scope. I am no supporter of the NRA, but in this case it is true to say
that “science doesn’t kill people; people kill people.” Science
contains no
such
directives. Religion is replete with them.
In her attempt to
equate bad science with bad religion, Robinson has recourse to the
laughable.
As a parallel to the fraud, hypocrisy and charlatanism religion has
committed in its
name (she declines to list them, from early Christian forgery of
documents to modern
televangelism and much in between), she offers—wait for it—the
Piltdown hoax and
“the long-credited
deception having to do with cloning in South Korea”! Then she offers this gem:
If by “science” is meant
authentic science, then “religion” must mean authentic religion,
granting the
difficulties in arriving at these definitions.
But in
authentic science there are
no
difficulties, because science
is a method, a set of principles of a universal and objective nature.
The fact
that mistakes can be made, or that some scientists can be less than
‘scientific’ (or even indulge in dishonesty) in the application of that
method, is beside the point. And it was other scientists who exposed
the Piltdown hoax. There is no such universality to
religion,
neither in method nor in principles. Every religion, every sect,
believes it
has the ‘authentic’ revelation and interpretation of its timeless and
unimpeachable holy books, and they are all mutually exclusive and
contradictory. There are no universal laws of religious faith
possessing objective controls, as there is in science. And since those
judgments of authenticity
usually
include the belittling, damning and destroying of those who believe
differently, I fail to see how Robinson can have the audacity to defend
the
very idea of ‘authenticity’ where religion is concerned. But then,
perhaps she
defines the term according to her personal set of dogmas.
Dawkins
and the Cambridge Theologians
After laying this
groundwork of
defamation, Robinson now enters upon the world of science herself, to
find in
it a support for her own anti-science stance, or at least against
science as alleged charlatans like Richard Dawkins champion it. She
starts by
accusing him
of
virtually being ignorant of “the physics of the last century or so,” by
which
she means the field of quantum theory. She immediately retracts
this by directing the reader to the final chapter where Dawkins does
address
quantum theory. The allegation, of course, still stands, somewhat like
the
objected-to remark by an attorney which the judge directs the jury to
disregard.
She calls attention
to
his use of physicality and
materiality as standards for determining the real and objective
existence of
anything, along with his use of commonplace experience as the standard
of
reasonableness and—a favorite word—probability. He does this despite
his
awareness that the physical and material are artifacts of the scale at
which
reality is achieved. For us, he says, “matter is a useful construct.”
This and
other material she
quotes shows that Dawkins is anything but ignorant of the physics of
the last
century, belying her lead-in statement (which the jury should indeed
disregard). But we can now see where she is leading the reader. First
of all, Dawkins
himself, she says, must acknowledge that “the image of deeper reality
invoked
by him” may in fact mean that the human brain’s innate sense of “dualism”
(our tendency to subjectively distinguish between ‘mind’
and ‘body’ which Dawkins has offered as one explanation
for religious belief) is
something which
“prepares us to believe in a ‘soul’ which inhabits the body rather than
being
integrally part of the body.” But there is a big difference between “a
fluid
matter (which) momentarily comes together” but still
can support
through that fluidity and change of material a continuing sense of
‘I-ness’—between that and
matter
housing what religion maintains is a distinct supernatural soul created
separately by
God and destined for eternity with the same identity as the body it had
on
earth. Nothing Dawkins proposes justifies such an outlandish parallel
as
Robinson would like to foist on us.
Robinson declares
that she does
“not wish to recruit science to the cause of religion,” but that, it
seems to
me, is exactly what she is trying to do, and here she reaches the crux
of her
critique. Like everything else, she only intimates it, because she
never comes
right out to fully connect religion with what she is saying. She
accuses Dawkins
of a kind of Polyanna (my word) attitude toward everything:
Dawkins acknowledges no
difficulty. He has a simple-as-that, plain-as-day approach to the
grandest
questions, unencumbered by doubt, consistency, or countervailing
information.
Well,
Dawkins is certainly
confident, evincing little doubt in his various positions, especially
in regard
to the existence of God. (Note, however, that he titles his key
chapter, “Why
There Almost Certainly Is No God”—perhaps
there’s a bit of wiggle room being allowed here!) But Robinson thinks
to
perceive a fly in the ointment, and here is where she does indeed draw
on
science to discredit Dawkins’ thinking, which she claims “cannot
properly be
called scientific.” To discuss
what Robinson is getting at, I will need to quote an extensive passage
from
her, which will also lay out the basis of Dawkins’ argument against the
existence of God (the hiatuses are hers):
He reasons thus: A creator God
must be more complex than his creation, but this is impossible because
if he
existed he would be at the wrong end of evolutionary history. To be
present in
the beginning he must have been unevolved and therefore simple. Dawkins
is very
proud of this insight. He considers it unanswerable. He asks, “How do
they
[theists] cope with the argument that any God capable of designing a
universe,
carefully and foresightfully tuned to lead to our evolution, must be a
supremely complex and improbable entity who needs an even bigger
explanation
than the one he is supposed to provide?” And “if he [God] has the
powers
attributed to him he must have something far more elaborately and
non-randomly
constructed than the largest brain or the largest computer we know,”
and “a
first cause of everything…must have been simple and therefore, whatever
else we
call it, God is not an appropriate name (unless we very explicitly
divest it of
all the baggage that the word ‘God’ carries in the minds of most
religious
believers).” At Cambridge, says Dawkins, “I challenged the theologians to
answer the
point that a God capable of designing a universe, or anything else,
would have
to be complex and statistically improbable. The strongest response I
heard was
that I was brutally foisting a scientific epistemology upon an
unwilling
theology.” Dawkins is clearly innocent of this charge against him.
Whatever is
being foisted here, it is not a scientific epistemology.
Evolution is the creature of
time. And, as Dawkins notes, modern cosmologies generally suggest that
time and
the universe as a whole came into being together. So a creator cannot
very well
be thought of as having attained complexity through a process of
evolution.
That is to say, theists need find no anomaly in a divine “complexity”
over
against the “simplicity” that is presumed to characterize the universe
at its
origin. (I use these terms not because I find them appropriate to the
question
but because Dawkins uses them, and my point is to demonstrate the flaws
in his
reasoning.) In this context, Dawkins cannot concede, even
hypothetically, a
reality that is not time-bound, that does not conform to Darwinism as
he
understands it. Yet in an earlier book, Unweaving
the Rainbow, Dawkins remarks that “further developments of the [big
bang]
theory, supported by all available evidence, suggest that time itself
began in
this mother of all cataclysms. You probably don’t understand, and I
certainly
don’t, what it can possibly mean to say that time itself began at a
particular
moment. But once again, that is a limitation of our minds….” That God
exists
outside time as its creator is an ancient given of theology. The
faithful are
accustomed to expressions like “from everlasting to everlasting” in
reference
to God, language that the positivists would surely have considered
nonsense but
that does indeed express the intuition that time is an aspect of the created order. Again, I do not wish to
abuse either theology or scientific theory by implying that either can
be used
as evidence in support of the other; I mean only that the big bang in
fact
provides a metaphor that might help Dawkins understand why his grand
assault on
the “God Hypothesis” has failed to impress the theists.
Now we can take it
apart.
Robinsons claims that Dawkins’ arguments against the theologians are
not
scientific epistemology, that this is not scientific reasoning being
brought to
the question. What, then, is it in Robinson’s estimation?
Dawkins
and his
reasoning/evidence is time-bound, in that the concept of evolution is
dependent
on the workings of time, and time only came into existence with the
known
universe following the Big Bang. Therefore, the Creator’s ‘complexity’
cannot be
tied to a process of evolution which entails the time factor. We
cannot
disallow a complex God by requiring him to exist and operate by the
material universe’s processes. Robinson admits that the language she is
using is
not
appropriate to the question, but she must do so because Dawkins uses it
and to
demonstrate the flaws in his reasoning. But right there, she has thrown
a light
on her own, and religion’s, flaws in reasoning. Dawkins—and herself by
default—use such language and concepts because they are the only thing
we have.
We have no way of knowing, let alone claiming with a priori
certainty, that there is another type of complexity
possible, through other types of processes not involving time, or that
complexity can exist in this other pre-physical/material domain without any processes of evolution at
all. To maintain this is simply to declare it by fiat,
which Dawkins rightly criticizes. What Robinson is doing,
once again like all her apologist compatriots, is defining
God arbitrarily (without remotely understanding it) as something that
exists and functions ‘outside’ or
‘above’ everything that we can possibly know or even conceive of. She
is
faulting Dawkins—and calling him a faux or pseudo or hysterical
scientist—for
not doing the same as she! When Dawkins challenged the Cambridge
theologians he
was asking for some kind of evidence, some theoretical conceptual
argument, as
to how God could function as creator, since this would by any logical
or
experiential measure require some form of complexity. He offered them,
as an
example, the only complexity known and demonstrable by science: the
principle
of evolution from simplicity to complexity, which necessarily entails
the
factor of time. Every process from the Big Bang onwards has moved on
that
one-way path. To postulate complexity as pre-existing without any such
process
of development goes against everything we have learned. Dawkins was
simply
asking the theologians to explain or describe God’s brand of
complexity, if not by
Darwinian evolutionary principles and the input of time, then by some
other
process or concept. Of course, they could not. They would have no basis
on which
to do so
(other than simply religious faith). If Robinson, appealing to ‘proper
scientific epistemology’ is going to disallow time-based evolution as
legitimately applicable to the question of God’s complexity, she has at
least to offer some alternative source or reasoning for a pre-existing
complex
God who
could create the universe—not simply declare it to be, or to be
hypothetically
possible (which, of course, is her only available option). In her
world, anything could be hypothetically
possible, no matter how lacking in evidence or
conceivability—particularly if
it had the blessing of religion.
But on
what basis can she, or
any theologian, occupy such a position? Dawkins is indeed imposing
science on
an unwilling theology—unwilling, because theology has never had any
sort of
epistemology to appeal to! Epistemology is “the study of the origins,
nature,
methods and limits of human knowledge.”
But there is no “study”
here, since there is no possibility of ‘understanding’ what is being attributed to God. What are the
theological origins and methods? The words of an ancient
holy
book? Personal experiences of God’s voice in believers’ heads? (These
the Cambridge theologians actually put forward!) A lack of
understanding
(those gaps that are ever narrowing) of how the world works which
invite God as
an explanation? Because religious beliefs are traditional, ingrained,
and the
conviction that we need them and want them compels us to perpetuate
them? These
are the very fallacies that Dawkins exposes and dismantles in his book,
fallacies which theologians, along with Robinson, never acknowledge to
the slightest degree.
Robinson’s
claim for a
different brand of complexity for God—an entity who never has to follow any rules or
reason—is
the central, if only, plank in
the
platform she creates to stand on. She thinks to have caught out Dawkins
in some
blatant error of reasoning. “In this context [science’s Darwinian
outlook tied
to a time-bound universe], Dawkins cannot concede, even
hypothetically,
a
reality that is not time-bound, that does not conform to Darwinism as
he
understands it.” True, he cannot, because nothing in the universe’s
experience
would bring one to consider it possible. This is not to say that
“possible” it
could not be—although we have nothing but arbitrary fiat based on
wishful
thinking to suggest that it actually is.
Yet Robinson is guilty of a far greater error of reasoning in
suggesting the
reverse of the coin, that we ought (yes, ought, since Dawkins is
‘guilty’ of
not doing so) to concede the possibility of a supra- or pre-universe
reality not
time-bound, inhabited by an innately complex God, because she has no
tangible
reason for insisting on that concession. Other than, of course,
traditional beliefs
that were set down in a primitive, pre-scientific phase of human
evolution, beliefs for
which
modern science (including Dawkins in this book) has
provided
a host of insights and evidence to explain their development
as human
phenomena with no perceptible link to reality. Dawkins is far
more
justified in refusing to concede a God-inhabited hypothetical reality
outside time
and the rules of complexity than Robinson is in postulating the actual
existence of one. He is justified by the only objective measure we
have: our knowledge
and
experience of the universe as uncovered by science.
Of
Dawkins Robinson demands facts and evidence. Of herself, she merely
demands
hypotheticals and speculations. She imagines that this is a fair and
balanced
match-up. (This is exactly what Daniel Dennett means when he says
debating a
religionist is like playing tennis with someone who lowers the net for
their
shots and raises it for yours.)
Robinson
goes on to illustrate
the skyhook she is hanging from. Does she even attempt a reasoned
justification
for her position?
That God exists outside time as
its creator is an ancient given of theology.
Perhaps
she is claiming that
ancient axioms like this are self-evident, and don’t require anything
resembling
objective evidence or justification; that they didn’t suffer from the
lack of accurate
knowledge about the universe which modern science has given us (in
stark
contrast to the ‘science’ and philosophy developed by the ancients
themselves,
long consigned, for the most part, to the dustbin of dead ideas). In
her
critique, she has failed to address the drubbing Dawkins (and others)
have given to all the standard ‘proofs’ for the existence
of God. She is no better than the theist debater who, outmatched by
scientific
arguments at every turn, declares from his boxed-in corner that God
simply is the way we declare him because he
follows no rules of logic or evidence that we are a party to.
I would
liken it to sailors
stumbling upon a desert island where they find two stranded people: a
man and a
baby. Some of the sailors declare that the man must have given birth to
the
baby, even though this contradicts everything we know about birth.
(Perhaps
they have been led to this declaration by some words in their holy
book.) Other
sailors who search for evidence that a woman was recently on the
island, who
perhaps drowned when trying to swim to civilization, or that the baby
was
dropped from a plane in a box, are criticized and ridiculed by the
first group
for not conceding the possibility that this man and this birth are
unique, not
subject to the universal rules that experience has always obeyed. (To
complicate things, the stranded man cannot be medically examined or
questioned.) Robinson and the Cambridge theologians would have us believe—indeed, have
us assume
as a given, perhaps based on some outlandish ancient theories about
procreation—that a man can
give
birth to a baby. Theoretically, I suppose it would be ‘hypothetically
possible’
that this particular man gave birth because he was a unique mutation,
or perhaps he was really an androgynous
alien in
disguise, or the island’s volcano spewed out molecules which just
happened to
form a man with a self-fertilizing womb, but anyone who would seriously
put
forward such
alternate ‘explanations’ would be considered bonkers—that
is, in
any other area but religion. That, too, is
Dawkins’ point. And it is
indeed why, in Robinson's snide words, that
Dawkins’ “assault on the ‘God Hypothesis’ has failed to impress the
theists.”
Quantum Theory: God’s Newest “Gap”
But there is more to all this
than meets the reader’s eye. Robinson does indeed have an Ace up her
sleeve,
but she produces it only by implication. That Ace is quantum theory,
and with
it she is in fact doing what she says she does not wish to, “recruit
science to
the cause of religion.” The trouble is, she never lays it out for
rational
consideration. It is left to cast its shadow over other parts of the
piece.
Let’s see if we can bring it into the light.
Robinson has spoken of “the
fact of quantum theory and certain of its implications,” which she has
accused
Dawkins of ignoring. According to her, he has produced work that has
not been
“informed” by this dimension of the physics of the last century. (As I
said
earlier, she then points to his final chapter, which belies her
statement.) It
follows that she must regard quantum theory as providing a
justification for
postulating God’s existence. Those “implications” apparently give us a
rationale for locating him in a world which is not limited by the laws
of the
one we perceive, laws which Dawkins has appealed to as disproving any
likelihood of God’s existence. The key phrase embodying her implied
position is
this:
…especially
(Dawkins’) use of physicality and materiality as standards for
determining the
real and objective existence of anything.
She is eager to agree with
him that physicality and materiality are features of “the scale at
which
reality is perceived,” the scale on which we live, observe and
experience, one
of very narrow limits within the range of all that there is, and
following laws
which the inner world of the quantum does not seem to. In view of her
treatment
of Dawkins’ argument against a complex Deity (the long passage I quoted
above),
it seems evident that she is suggesting the world of the quantum as the
dwelling place of God where that argument need not apply. Since the
scientific
rules of our physical/material experience do not seem to be a part of
the
quantum dimension of reality, indeed if physicality and materiality
themselves
are features only of our outer world, and since she insists on the
legitimacy
of postulating a complex God that does not need to obey the rules of
materiality and evolution, an intended association of the two seems
evident.
Thus, God does not lie ‘above’ or ‘outside’ the perceivable rule- and
time-bound universe, but inside it—so far inside that his and its
modes of
behavior are unlike anything on our outer scale.
Now,
I am not going to label
myself a scientist, much less an expert on quantum theory (any more, I
imagine,
than Robinson is, which is perhaps why she does not attempt to spell
out her
implications), but I can draw on a limited knowledge of it, together
with a life-long respect for science and
the
analytical thinking it promotes, unencumbered by the distortions
created by
religious faith. In regard to the world of quantum theory, Dawkins says
this in
his book:
Our
imaginations are not yet tooled-up to penetrate the neighbourhood of
the quantum.
Nothing at that scale behaves in the way matter—as we are evolved to
think—ought to behave….Quantum mechanics, that rarefied pinnacle of
twentieth-century scientific achievement, makes brilliantly successful
predictions about the real world. This predictive success seems to mean
that
quantum theory has got to be true in some sense; as true as anything we
know,
even including the most down-to-earth common-sense facts. Yet the assumptions that quantum theory needs to
make, in order to deliver those predictions, are so mysterious that
even the
great Feynman himself was moved to remark: ‘If you think you understand
quantum
theory, you don’t understand quantum theory.’ [p.363-5]
One of the popular
impressions (which I share) about quantum mechanics is that the
behavior of
entities at the sub-atomic level is subject to an “uncertainty
principle.” There,
things seem to occur at random, following no predictable pattern by the
standards of the larger scale—our ‘real world,’ as Dawkins refers to it
in the
above quote. Some scientists, as I recall, speak only of indeterminate,
or ‘potentials’
of
behavior at that level; in certain experiments, a ‘choice’ of behavior
is only
effected by the
act of observation from outside, from our world. If the world of the
quantum is
unreachable by our larger-scale conditioned minds, could we not be
peering into
the domain of God? Some religiously-oriented scientists have actually
proposed
this, though it is not always clear what type of ‘religious
orientation’ they
are holding; it perhaps includes a good measure of the Einsteinian
variety (without a personal God), as
discussed in my review of The God
Delusion.
But if Robinson thinks to
claim that inner domain for a God of more orthodox nature, she is
opening up a
can of quantum worms. If the essence of quantum behavior is randomness
and the
essence of the physical is predictability, with laws of nature that can
be
comprehended and depended upon, this may be a paradox we lack
understanding of
(as yet), but it exists nonetheless; we can observe it. Paradox or not,
the random
unpredictable
world of the quantum produces the non-random predictable world of our
large-scale materiality. This is as much a this-universe process as
anything
else, regardless of whether we know, or even can know, how it works. By
locating God in this as yet ill-understood inner world, Robinson is
simply
guilty of yet another recourse to “the God of the gaps” fallacy. We
don’t
understand the nitty-gritty of quantum mechanics, so that’s where God
resides and does
his work.
This, however, removes God from
the supernatural. He becomes part of the natural world and amenable
(once we
further unlock the quantum dimension) to scientific investigation. This
would
certainly destroy the “separate magisteriums” position, and scientists
(rather
than theologians) would be responsible for defining and revealing
God—requiring
Robinson to considerably revamp the tenor of her critique.
But slotting God between the
quarks is not the same as observing God directly. It is still the
postulation
of something for which there is no direct evidence, but only an
interpretation
convenient for theists. Scientists, on the other hand, can to some
degree uncover the
quantum; that
is how they know of its randomness and the fact that such randomness
produces predictability.
No scientist has simply postulated randomness as an explanation for
predictability because it is convenient. But ‘God’ as
an
explanation for how randomness produces predictability is no
explanation at
all, since we still must define God and his nature within that inner
world. If
he is simply synonymous with it, then he is not a personal,
self-conscious God,
but only the personification of the non-conscious workings of the
quantum
level. If the essence of the quantum is random unpredictability and God
is a
part of that world, he must by nature act and think in random ways. (He
would
be far more “hysterical” than science or Dawkins!) He might be innately
complex,
but how
can a random-behaving entity produce creation through a personal,
conscious
decision? If he is not bound by the quantum behavior of his world, then
he is
not a part of it, but must lie ‘outside’ that inner world—and thus we
are back
at square one, with no conceptual explanation of how this works and no
basis on
which to “concede” its possibility.
Robinson might insist on the
qualification she expressed earlier, saying that all this reasoning,
and the
language employed to present it, contains ‘our-world’ features and may
not
properly apply to the workings of a quantum God. Maybe so, but that
leaves us
with no means of evaluating or even discussing the subject except to
declare it
by fiat, and thus we have returned to another square one.
The
Science of Ethics
Robinson
now moves on to Dawkins’ treatment of ethics
and the Bible. She does not attempt any rebuttal to his judgment of the
Old
Testament as “barbarous and abhorrent,” except that she is anxious to
discredit
one particular claim: that ancient Jewish attitudes in regard to the
Ten
Commandments were directed only at fellow Jews, that “Love Thy
Neighbor” was
not some universal directive to love one’s fellow man and woman of any
ethnic
group but only one’s own countrymen. This is the sole topic concerning
which
Dawkins draws on the work of John Hartung in the latter’s study, “Love Thy
Neighbor: The
Evolution of In-Group Morality,” despite Robinson’s misleading
declaration that
Dawkins’ treatment of “these texts” (referring to his views on the Old
Testament
and New Testament in general) “depends to a striking degree” on
Hartung’s
paper. This is another dishonest tactic, associating as much as
possible with a
source one thinks can be discredited in order to taint everything.
There is
also a subtle attempt to once again conjure up the specter of
anti-Semitism,
pinning it on Hartung as well. Studies which call into doubt the
idealized
picture of Old Testament morality—and it happens in regard to
questioning
biblical history as well, or pre-Exilic Hebrew monotheism—are “murky
waters,
the kind toward which Darwinism has often tended to migrate.” So now
all of
science, particularly its dirty old grandfather, is to be tarred with
the same
anti-Semitic brush for the sin of questioning the Bible’s purity and
integrity.
Robinson
attempts an exegetical refutation of
Hartung’s and Dawkins’ contention that ‘Love Thy Neighbor’ in the
Bible’s
ethical teachings “was originally intended to apply only to a
narrowly-defined
in-group”:
“[quoting Dawkins]‘Love thy
neighbor’ didn’t mean what
we now think it means. It meant only ‘Love another Jew’.” As for the
New
Testament interpretation of the text, “Hartung puts it more bluntly
than I
dare: ‘Jesus would have turned over in his grave if he had known that
Paul
would be taking his plan to the pigs.’ ” Pigs being, of course,
gentiles.
First
she tries to rescue ‘Love Thy Neighbor’. She
starts by admitting that Leviticus 19:18 does allow for the narrow
interpretation: “[it] does indeed begin, ‘You shall not take vengeance
or bear
a grudge against any of your people’,” then thinks to counter this with
Leviticus 19:33-34: “ ‘When an alien resides with you in your land, you
shall
not oppress the alien....You shall love the alien as yourself.’ ” But
Robinson
is putting her own spin on these verses, claiming that, in light of
them, “it
is wrong by Dawkins’s/Hartung’s own standards to argue that the ethos
of the
law does not imply moral consideration for others.” This is an
implication of
universality, but the text offers no such thing. That becomes clear
when the
entire passage is quoted (the hiatus was hers):
Leviticus 19:33-34 [NEB]: When an
alien settles with you in your land, you shall not oppress him. He
shall be
treated as a native born among you, and you shall love him as a man
like
yourself, because you were aliens in Egypt.
The
passage merely says that when a foreigner comes to
live with you—in other words, becomes a countryman (an
immigrant)—you are
to extend the same treatment to him as you give to your fellow Hebrews.
The
standard is whether the one to be loved is a countryman, a
“native born among you,” or an equivalent, not
simply any
human
being. It may represent, in this special case, opening a gate in the
fence
surrounding the in-group, but it hardly represents an ethic tantamount
to
universal brotherly love. In any case, the Old Testament is too full of
conquest, genocide, vitriol against other peoples of the region for
their
worship of false gods and their enticement of Hebrews to such
practices, as well as
dire warnings to a series of foreign conquerors who will be utterly
overcome
once the Messiah arrives to set Israel and its God over all lands, ever
to imagine
that any Hebrew text advocated universal love toward all humanity.
In a
similar vein, Robinson is also unaware that Jesus in the Gospel of John
preaches no general principle of ‘Love Thy Neighbor.’ His admonition to his apostles to “love one another” is an in-house rule, not a
universal moral dictum; 13:35 shows that he is simply advocating love
among his followers, who are part of an in-group elect, so that “all will know that you are my disciples.”
But
her actual appeal to the New Testament is an outright
blunder:
Jesus provided a gloss on 19:18,
the famous Parable of
the Good Samaritan. With specific reference to this verse, a lawyer
asks Jesus,
“And who is my neighbor?” Jesus tells a story that moves the lawyer to
answer
that the merciful Samaritan—a non-Jew—embodies the word “neighbor.”
That the
question would be posed to Jesus, or by Luke, is evidence that the
meaning of
the law was not obvious or settled in antiquity.
The
parable of the Good Samaritan is found only in Luke
(which she seems to realize)
and is generally considered by critical scholars of the New Testament
to be
Luke’s product, not spoken by Jesus. And why did Luke find this “gloss”
necessary? Because Luke was part of a gentile Christian community and
in his
Gospel (probably written in the early 2nd
century) he regularly
features elements that reflect and serve gentile interests. Moreover,
the fact
that he felt constrained to place such a ‘lesson’ in Jesus’ mouth would
indicate the opposite of Robinson’s conclusion: that Jews in general
were still
not inclusionary by nature and that
the meaning of the Law was, for them, indeed settled—with an in-group
understanding. Luke's Jesus had to correct that position.
There
used to be a traditional line of Christian
thinking, extending into modern scholarship, that the Jews of the
pre-Christian
era held the concept of themselves as God’s agent of universal
atonement, that
they were undergoing their historical sufferings in order to redeem
both Jews
and gentiles. The so-called Suffering Servant Song of Isaiah 53 was the
prime
text supposed to contain this selfless philosophy. More clear-eyed
critical scholars
of the latter 20th century showed that this
was not the case, that
the texts have been forced into this interpretation. (See, for example,
Harry
M. Orlinsky: The So-Called ‘Servant of
the Lord’ and ‘Suffering Servant’ in Second Isaiah, and R. N.
Whybray: Isaiah 40-66.) It began with certain early
Christians who thought to read their own universalist theory of
salvation
about the
sacrifice of Jesus back into Jewish literature and thinking; it was
part of
their
wish to see the entire Hebrew scriptures as a presaging of Christ. But
it was
and is entirely unrealistic to expect that the ancient Hebrews would
have had
such an outlook, and it is no criticism of them that they did not.
As
for Hartung’s “pigs,” does Robinson not know the
source of this characterization of gentiles and outcasts? Hartung is
simply
echoing Jesus himself. Matthew (7:6), as part of his Sermon on the
Mount, has
Jesus say: “Do not give dogs what is holy; and do not throw your pearls
before
swine…” Commentators have tended to worry over this passage and wonder
how
such
in-group attitudes can fit with the standard picture of a universalist
Jesus.
Reginald H. Fuller (Harper’s—ironically!—Bible
Commentary) suggests: “It must be an expression of the
exclusiveness of the narrowly Jewish Christian community that
formulated (this
Matthean) tradition.” (Perhaps an authentic
dissing of the Jewish heritage; it slips in in more than one New
Testament commentator’s treatment of Christian
morality.)
In
view of Robinson’s naïve attitude toward scripture,
it is too easy to turn her own scornful remark about Dawkins back on
its
speaker:
In general, Dawkins’s air of
genteel familiarity with
Scripture, though becoming in one aware as he is of its contributions
to the
arts, dissipates under the slightest scrutiny.
The
one thing worse than ignorance is pompous
ignorance.
The Evolution of
Morality
Strangely,
Robinson is even offended at Dawkins’ view
that humanity’s moral consensus (the Zeitgeist:
spirit of the times) is ever evolving and improving, and has noticeably
done so
over the last couple of centuries. (Perhaps because such a view
undermines the
timeless quality of biblical ethics.) She accuses Dawkins of a
“consistent
inattention to history,” disagreeing with his statement that Hitler’s
extreme
anti-Semitism was not as far outside the Zeitgeist of his time as it
would be
in our own day. She appeals to a curious entry in the Encyclopedia
Britannica
which describes anti-Semitism in pre-war Germany as “a theory
of nationality and a fad…(which did not) exercise much influence” until
it was
brought to the fore by Hitler. This is errant nonsense. Anti-Semitism,
reflected in everything from the Dreyfus Affair in 1890s France to the
turning
away of Jewish refugee ships from American shores in the 1930s speaks
to a
continuous endemic prejudice against Jews whose roots go back through
centuries
of Christian persecution of the unfortunate Jew as a Christ-killer.
(Robinson
would likely be keen to deny the latter.)
Her
tactics are clear in disputing another of Dawkins’
examples of sub-standard (by our measure) ethics in regard to race in
the quite
recent past. Dawkins quotes T. H. Huxley, a respected English biologist
contemporary with Darwin, who judged the black man to be mentally
inferior to
the white. Robinson objects that Huxley was not in the vanguard of his
time,
that he was dismissing “standards that had long been salient among his
contemporaries.” She specifically allots such salient higher standards
to the
emancipationists (in both Europe and America) of the latter's Civil War
period:
The vanguard in the period in
which Huxley wrote
[1865] were those Christian abolitionists whose intentions he dismissed
as, of
course, at odds with science.
Oh?
Robinson is being perversely selective here. Not
only does she not offer any contemporary writer to back up her claim,
not only
does she fail to quote writings of the time that directly took
exception to
such as Huxley’s alleged “atavistic” denial of current standards
(Huxley would
have
been buried under an avalanche of such protest if he lived today), but
she
conveniently ignores Dawkins’ arresting quotation from Abraham Lincoln,
surely
the leading emancipationist of his time and certainly a Christian.
Lincoln
makes no direct appeal to science in stating his opinions about racial
equality, saying this in an 1858 debate with Stephen A. Douglas:
I am not, nor ever have been, in
favor of bringing
about in any way the social and political equality of the white and
black
races…I will say, in addition to this, that there is a physical
difference
between the white and black races [no
indication that this opinion is
determined by Lincoln’s view of ‘science’] which I believe will
forever
forbid
the two races living together on terms of social and political
equality…while
they do remain together there must be the position of superior and
inferior,
and I as much as any other man am in
favor of having the superior position assigned to the white race.
[p.267]
Those
italics (my own) would indicate that Lincoln and
Huxley did indeed represent prevailing standards of the day.
Robinson
equally ignores other examples offered by
Dawkins to show that in regard to our sense of morality, our treatment
of
animals, our behavior in war and even concerns for our own troops in
battle,
the Zeitgeist has indeed
moved on dramatically. (Compare public concern
for the
few thousand Americans killed so far in Iraq with the wholesale
slaughter of
hundreds of thousands of British soldiers in repeatedly fruitless
charges
against enemy trenches which should have earned their commander,
Douglas Haig,
the gallows after World War I; he was neither removed nor faulted.)
The
fact that Robinson would go to these lengths to
dispute (and mendaciously) such an evident phenomenon as modern moral
progress—concurrent
with overall progress in science and humanism—is telling, not only for
her
prejudice against Dawkins, but for her skewed world-view as determined
by her
religious sympathies. The Harper’s
editor who approved this piece either shared in those sympathies, or
was asleep
at the switch.
Not
surprisingly, Robinson takes exception to Dawkins’
contention that atheism does not produce wars (as opposed to the many
religious
wars in history). He asks: “Why would anyone go to war for the sake of
an absence of belief?” She fails to supply a
single example of a war inspired by atheism, but nothing daunted, she
proceeds to redefine “war” (lamenting its traditional meaning as “a
peculiarity
of language”) to encompass any internal “violence against religion,”
such as in
the French Revolution, or under the Soviet Union and China. Her
semantic inventiveness is certainly in evidence here…
In three of these instances the extirpation
of
religion was part of a program to reshape society by excluding certain
forms of
thought, by creating an absence of belief.
…but
so is the transparency of her contortions. Her
examples belong rather to the realm of persecution, attacks on
‘heretics’ in
the service of a political ideology,
and in fact are paralleled by countless examples of that very thing in religious settings. Considering that
Dawkins made his statement in the context of international relations
(proceeding out of his examination of the dubious claim that Hitler was
an
atheist, in which he offers several revealing quotes recording Hitler
expressing
Christian sentiments), it is hardly kosher for Robinson to artificially
inject
a different category entirely. But it is typical. From it, she draws
“the
kindest conclusion…that Dawkins has not acquainted himself with the
history of
modern authoritarianism.” One can only cringe at such unctuous
hypocrisy.
Tolerance and the Children
But
worse is yet to come. As her parting shot,
Robinson accuses Dawkins of “a bold attack on tolerance” for
criticizing
society’s practice of permitting people to rear their children in their
own
religious traditions. Dawkins has been at pains to point out the
injustice of
indoctrinating children in beliefs and practices which they are not in
a
position to evaluate for themselves, imposing artificial and socially
divisive
identities on them, as well as prejudices, fears, and irrationalities
from
which they may consequently never be in a position to gain freedom.
Amid stark
examples of such objectionable effects, Robinson seizes on one case in
particular which Dawkins allegedly “turns a cold eye on”: the Amish.
Here,
again, misrepresentation abounds. Dawkins’ diatribe is actually against
those
who defend the enforced indoctrination of children as a desirable
feature of a
supposedly valuable “cultural diversity” within society. On that altar,
for
example, the Amish are said to be justified (and the court system
allows it) in
barring their children from a high school education, from taking part
in modern
civilization, medicine, and amenities like electricity. Trapping these
children “in
a 17th century time-warp” in order to
maintain that “cultural
diversity” and their parents’ right to so restrict their lives Dawkins
rightly
finds reprehensible, but Robinson labels it an attack on tolerance! She
goes so
far as to defend the poor disparaged Amish by calling attention to
their
“pacifist way of life (which) hardly burdens the planet,” as though
that would
justify the children’s enforced fate. And she faults Dawkins for “not
even
mentioning” this.
Perhaps
Dawkins failed to do so because he was too
busy mentioning—Robinson never does—the disastrous and crippling
effects on
Christian and Muslim children who are brought up to believe everyone
outside
their own faith is a damned infidel, who are taught that society must
be
returned to medieval ignorance and superstition, who may be trained to
be
suicide
martyrs and chant death to other nations. The faint voice of Amish
pacifism is
buried under a torrent of bigotry, hatred, exclusionism, war and
destruction—none of it the product of today’s atheism or science. This
is as
shamefully dishonest a book critique as I have ever encountered. In
that,
Robinson maintains the honored tradition of most apologetic discourse.
In
her final paragraph, she notes Dawkins’ theory of
“memes…mind viruses highly analogous to genes.” Here she puts her most
distorted spin on Dawkins’ material, claiming the implication that
“there are
more than sentimental reasons for valuing the diversity that he
derides.” She
first suggests that if genes tend to
work for their physical survival and achieve it because their effect on
the
organism they are a part of is somehow “fit” (implying ‘good’), then
perhaps we
need to accord the same respect to memes.
Ideas that have survived and spread must also be considered good.
To
quote Dawkins, “this
sounds terrific—right up until you
give it a moment’s thought.” The male instinct to rape, for example, an
idea or
physical
impulse (take your pick) which has survived through primate history and
is
still going strong today, is hardly to be lauded, by either geneticists
or
memeticists. But is it not part of the human diversity of behavior?
Should we
not, according to Robinson, strive to keep it alive? She makes it sound
like
scientists such as Dawkins wish to suppress all
diversity in human culture or belief. Instead, they want to be
selective, to
judge what is good and what is bad, to weed out the harmful from the
beneficial, which would still leave a diversity to satisfy the
heartiest
appetite. Besides, is religion a champion of diversity? Do American
Christians
regard other religions as their equal, do they value them for the
richness of diversity they
give to the human spiritual tapestry (a scientist might call it “the genome of the human
spirit”)? They are more likely to
advocate
Robinson’s “narrowing” of diversity through genocide, persecution and
forced
conversion. (Remember Ann Coulter’s “we should invade their
countries, kill their
leaders and
convert them all to Christianity”?) It is execrable for
Robinson to
impute to
Dawkins motives and tendencies of thought on a par with “the worst
errors of
eugenics at the cultural and intellectual level.” The ‘worst’ he
advocates is
education, the teaching of critical thinking, the cessation of
indoctrination
of children at young and vulnerable ages, and the publication of books
like his
own that anyone can read and evaluate for themselves.
Serving
as a bookend with the opening title of the
piece, these are Robinson’s final words. The reader can judge whether
the form
of diversity Robinson champions to “stabilize culture” is something that
could be called stable, or promises to build future stability.
It is diversity that makes any
natural system robust,
and diversity that stabilizes culture against the eccentricity and
arrogance
that have so often called themselves reason and science.
As
for the perils of the latter, she refrains
from quoting Martin Luther’s advice on the matter, as presented by
Dawkins:
“Whoever wants to be a Christian should tear the eyes out of his
reason.” And
“Reason is the greatest enemy that faith has…[it] should be destroyed
in all
Christians.” But she need not worry. She can never be accused of having
succumbed to the temptations of either reason or science. Her own
eccentricity and
arrogance have much more hallowed origins.
*
Earl Doherty
(with a few suggestions from my good friend Richard Young, who
was as incensed at this sham review as I was)
Age of Reason Home
Page
New Items